From the Open-Publishing Calendar
From the Open-Publishing Newswire
Indybay Feature
Greed as a Motor of Modern Society
Aristotle had already cricized it in his Nicomachean Ethics as Pleonexia, the constant urge to get more, with powerful words throughout history. Aristotle's cricism of greed, pleonexia, the desire to have more than you ever need, is based on an understanding of the polical which our society no longer shares...
GREED AS A MOTOR OF MODERN SOCIETY
By Nikolaus Egel
[This arcle is translated from the German on the Internet, http://www.academia.edu .]
Donald Trump already clearly presented his leading polical maxim to us on January 9, 2016 during an elecon campaign speech in Des Moines, Iowa. To thunderous applause of his hearers, he said:
“My whole life I’ve been greedy, greedy, greedy. I grabbed all the money I could get.
I’m so greedy. But now I want to be greedy for the United States.”
That such a Machiavellian-Hobbesian theorem of the current president of the world's
greatest superpower can be formulated quite openly as a polical program is so
astonishing and at the same me so characterisc of our me and society that it
deserves consideraon.
Especially since the Trump-crical journalist Ezra Klein (in contrast to Trump's remarks)
posted this quote on Facebook already on 29th January 2016 with the foresighted
remark that exactly this open greed will be an argument for Trump's elecon victory:
"This is why he's winning." Ezra Klein (as we now know) was undoubtedly right about
that. Donald Trump won the presidenal elecons, possibly because he – where other
policians as well as journalists sll feel compelled to at least maintain certain moral
standards – quite openly describes the driving force of our society: greed, since
anquity condemned as socially endangering and disintegrang, declared by Chrisanity
as one of the seven deadly sins, today a cardinal virtue that makes elecon victory
possible. Free with Kurt Vonnegut: That's how it works.
At least Trump cannot be accused of lying - at the latest since Augusne not a mortal
sin, but a serious sin. Which may be a reason for his elecon victory. It will now be
difficult for policians and the press to deal with this man and the polical
establishment he stands for, and we can be curious to see how the public polical scene
and the newspapers will react to this. The public bustle of policians and journalists will
now have to take a new direcon. We are curious. For a cynic "to whom nothing human
is alien”, these are interesng mes, especially because – as Balthasar Gracian has put it
in his Art of Worldly Wisdom: "More is now required to deal with a single human being
in these mes than with an enre people in previous mes.”
Nevertheless, this quotaon from Donald Trump makes one think and is (if we are not
yet complete cynics) depressing. Aſter all, in the past almost all philosophers and
policians spoke out against greed and condemned it with the strongest words.
Aristotle had already cricized it in his Nicomachean Ethics as Pleonexia, the constant
urge to get more, with powerful words throughout history. Aristotle's cricism of greed,
pleonexia, the desire to have more than you ever need, is based on an understanding of
the polical which our society no longer shares, but whose opposite (and with Trump's
successful words quite obviously) even seems to be the driving force and move behind
all acons.
Aristotle discusses pleonexia in the fiſth book of his Nicomachean Ethics in relaon to
jusce. For Aristotle, jusce is the highest of all virtues, because it is essenal and
necessary for the good and orderly coexistence of the cizens of a city or country. It is
the polical virtue par excellence. Without jusce, no polical coexistence is possible for
Aristotle, since the goal (telos) of man is in the polical organizaon:
"This is why jusce is considered the most important of all virtues, and neither the
evening star nor the morning star is so wonderful. In the proverb it is said 'Every virtue is
contained in righteousness'. And it is considered most of all perfect goodness of
character, because it is the exercise of perfect goodness. But it is perfect, because the
one who possesses it can also use the virtues in relaon to another human being, and
not only for himself. [...] Therefore, the saying of Bias that the exercise of a polical
office shows what kind of person someone is, is correct. For the one who holds a
polical office is already related to the other person and is already in a community. [...]
Jusce in this sense is now not a part of goodness of character, but the whole goodness,
and injusce as opposed to it is not a only part of badness, but the whole badness.”
Greed – let us follow Aristotle – destroys jusce and thus the polical foundaon on
which a society is based, which is why for Aristotle it is not only "a part of badness, but
all badness". For this reason, he condemns in the strictest terms those who strive for
more – the pleonektes, the greedy – because they want more than they deserve (in
relaon to the other cizens), which is why they are unjust and destrucve to society:
"On the one hand, those who violate the law (paranomos) are considered unjust, and on
the other hand those, who want more than they are entled to ( pleonektes), i.e. who
have an atude of inequality. [...] Since now the unjust wants to have more, he will
have to deal with goods, not with all goods, but with those to which outer happiness
(eutychia) and misfortune (atychia) refer, thus with goods which as such are always
goods, but not in every case for every man. People ask for them in prayers and chase
aſter them. However, they should not do this, but rather they should ask that the things
that are goods in themselves are also goods for them, and then choose these.”
For Aristotle, greed – pleonexia – Is the highest form of injusce and thus the worst of
all vices, because it endangers the existence of a polical community. This is especially
true when leading polical officials are greedy and place parcular interests above the
common good. In Aristotle's concepon, the polical community of his me (the polis)
did not consist primarily in economic independence (as our understanding today
suggests) and in maximizing the profits of the individuals/instuons living in a polical
community (also these modern terms), but rather in securing a common and thus good
polical life for the cizens, which the hedonist endangers through his exaggerated
desire to have more than the others.
Even if the Romans generally dealt with moral and polical quesons more loosely than
their Greek predecessors, the (at least public) condemnaon of greed remained a basic
component of the polical discussion at that me. In this sense, Cicero (exemplary as
the best known public figure to us) already addressed the vice of greed in his work On
Dues (De officiis), in parcular in relaon to the officials important for each state.
Especially officials should not be out to enrich themselves personally, because –
following Aristotle – this leads to unjust acons, which endanger the existence of a
community:
"No vice is more repulsive than greed, especially among leading men and those who run
the state. To have the state as a source of income is not only shameful, but also criminal
and nefarious. […] But those who are at the head of the state cannot win the
benevolence of many more easily by any means than by absnence and self-control.”
Also for the Stoa and Epicureanism, as well as for the enre ancient philosophy greed
remained the basic evil par excellence, with the same argumentaon that we already
got to know from Aristotle and Cicero: Because it is unfair, puts personal interests above
the welfare of the community, and thus leads to profoundly apolical and asocial
results, which dissolves an exisng polical system: with all the resulng consequences
that are known in history (all this is not new, one reads only Thucydides, Plutarch and
Sueton for the Greek respecvely Roman anquity or Montaigne, Hobbes and
Grimmelshausen for the beginning of the modern era) and which are now announcing
themselves to us again.
Likewise, greed was of course condemned in Chrisanity, albeit less as polical
misconduct, but rather as a personal sin endangering the salvaon of the soul, which
was mostly characterized as an inordinate striving for earthly possessions and as a lack
of trust in God. Greed (avaria; cupiditas) belongs both to the catalogue of the seven
main vices and to the three temptaons. Following the biblical passage 1 Timothy 6:
"Greed is the root of all evil" greed was described as bad in itself. Moreover, on the
basis of Jacob 5 it was even condemned as a "blatant sin" which was even worse than
the deadly sins because greed promoted the exploitaon of the workers. Jacob says:
“Now listen, you rich people, weep and wail because of the misery that is coming on
you. Your wealth has roed, and moths have eaten your clothes. Your gold and silver are
corroded. Their corrosion will tesfy against you and eat your flesh like fire. You have
hoarded wealth in the last days. Look! The wages you failed to pay the workers who
mowed your fields are crying out against you. The cries of the harvesters have reached
the ears of the Lord Almighty. You have lived on earth in luxury and self-indulgence. You
have faened yourselves in the day of slaughter. You have condemned and murdered
the innocent one, who was not opposing you.”
In the Middle Ages, the cricism of greed received an even deeper weighng as a
reacon to the bourgeois economy of money and goods that had developed. In the 12th and 13th centuries, the mendicant orders of the Dominicans and Franciscans were
founded (each as a reacon to changing polical and economic circumstances), whose
principles of poverty (paupertas) were completely opposed to greed. Take for example a
text wrien in the middle of the 13th century: in this text Saint Francis himself goes in
search of poverty, which is called the "foundaon of all virtues" ( fundamentum omnium
virtutum). In her speech, poverty complains about the fact that her opponent, avaria,
understood as "an inordinate desire to acquire or retain wealth", masquerades under
the names of "disncon" ( discreo) and "foresight" (providena) – which we will sll
encounter in Hobbes – and corrupts people.
Here one could sll add infinitely many examples of the me, from Thomas of Aquinas
to Dante Alighieri, who leaves the desirous in the Divine comedy with their backs up in
the dust, because they are not allowed to look at God, to Bernardine of Siena, whose
sermons Poggio Bracciolini in Florence had used as an occasion to write in 1428 with his
Dialogue On Greed (De avaria) probably the most important trease of the
Renaissance on this subject. The point is clear: since anquity greed has been
condemned unl the late Middle Ages and the Renaissance because – following these
authors – It has been dangerous for society and disintegrang for each individual.
This view of man, his goals and human coexistence in general changed for the first me
systemacally and philosophically with Thomas Hobbes, whom we can see as the
theorist of a modern society, in whose wake (though probably without knowing it)
Donald Trump sll stands with his public affirmaon of greed – with the difference, of
course, that Hobbes' books were burned in Oxford while Donald Trump was applauded
for it. Machiavelli had already hinted at a new view of the human being, the polical as
a sector in its own – In which greed plays a fundamental and acon-movang role –
and its goals in his Principe and Discorsi, but Thomas Hobbes for the first me in his
Leviathan theorecally founded and analyzed the concept of a society in which we sll
live: A property market society in which atomized and completely dissociated individuals
meet, who are only held together by overcoming their respecve self-interest – which
Hobbes no longer quesons, but (due to and in extension of his experiences during the
English Civil War) is assumed to be given factually in the nature of man – by a strong
sovereign, the only power "that can frighten them all", in order to realize a single
polical goal: The desire for peace, which (according to Hobbes) can only be realized
through the limitaon of the greed of each individual, which is presumed in human
beings, by a strong sovereign.
In order to make clear this fundamentally new view of man and the emergence of
society at Hobbes, I will only allow myself to contrast Hobbes with Rousseau: At the
beginning of the second chapter of the Social Contract, Rousseau writes: "The oldest
and only natural social enty is the family [...]". Hobbes writes in De cive [On the
cizen], summarizing, as it were, the core of his enre anthropology: "We now want to
go back to the state of nature and assume that humans, like mushrooms, would
suddenly have grown out of the earth and grown up, without being obliged to each
other.” For Hobbes there is no polical goal to be realized among mankind, no
acceptance of man as a polical being who makes his life a fulfiled and happy life only
in living together with others. For Hobbes – who here subconsciously or consciously
describes his (and also our) me in the form of the "state of nature" – there is no happy
life anymore. There is only the limitaon of greed with all available means – mind you:
against human beings and their egoisc parcular interests, which are assumed to be
eternal, their striving for the will to have more and more.
This is the first me in history that Hobbes has clearly formulated and worked out the
drive of his and our me: According to Hobbes, what drives people, what only leads
them to create "that great Leviathan through art, called community or state," is
precisely that passion that has been condemned since anquity as pleonexia, as avaria,
as greed. Man submits to an overpowering state in order to be safe from his own greed
and the greed of others and not to have to be afraid anymore: The state as
administrator of our fear, the undisturbed enrichment as its basis. But behind this is also
the feeling that society is already so fluid or fragile that the behaviour of overly greedy
people forces all others to take part in the race for power over others. This
consideraon is both terrible and overwhelming: it is that arficial "let's make man"
which Hobbes was the first to think systemacally and clearly – with great concern and
deep aversion – and which he formulated as an aempt to overcome the terrible
condions of his me; and which is now the driving force and basis of our society: "My
whole life I've been greedy, greedy, greedy. I've grabbed all the money I could get. I'm
so greedy." With greed elecons are won today, this is the way polics is made today
quite openly.
Accordingly, John Locke and Adam Smith were to turn this brutal diagnosis, which
Hobbes sll formulated with concern and deep aversion, into a posive one only a lile
later and make it socially acceptable in public: Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Senments
(1759) describes how those who pursue only their own advantage are led by an
"invisible hand", so that they "without intending it, indeed without knowing it promote
the interest of society". And in his work The Wealth of Naons he formulates the
assumpon – destrucve for all of us in his succession and not only reckless, but
inhuman – that self-interest is the "cause and source" of public prosperity.
Here we have arrived – oppressively – in our me. In a present in which greed is not
only publicly declared a virtue with which the world is governed and with which
elecons are won, but also in which all other vices condemned for centuries seem to
have become virtues.
For the seven deadly sins are well known: lust, gluony, greed, sloth, wrath, envy and
pride. These sins – sll condemned in the latest Catechism of the Catholic Church –
seem to be the very qualies with which the world is currently governed and to which a
large part of the people – subconsciously or quite consciously, thus confirming Hobbes'
diagnosis – have subordinated themselves. These sins have become the motor of
modern society: "All my life I was greedy, greedy, greedy. I grabbed all the money I
could get. But now I want to be greedy for the United States. I want to collect all that
money. I will be greedy for the United States."
To close this arcle not with Donald Trump and his promise to his constuents, but with
a much older warning: "Watch out for false prophets. They come to you in sheep’s
clothing, but inwardly they are ferocious wolves. By their fruit you will recognize them."
This is a warning that will also have been wrien in the two Bibles on which Donald
Trump laid his hand during his inauguraon.
By Nikolaus Egel
[This arcle is translated from the German on the Internet, http://www.academia.edu .]
Donald Trump already clearly presented his leading polical maxim to us on January 9, 2016 during an elecon campaign speech in Des Moines, Iowa. To thunderous applause of his hearers, he said:
“My whole life I’ve been greedy, greedy, greedy. I grabbed all the money I could get.
I’m so greedy. But now I want to be greedy for the United States.”
That such a Machiavellian-Hobbesian theorem of the current president of the world's
greatest superpower can be formulated quite openly as a polical program is so
astonishing and at the same me so characterisc of our me and society that it
deserves consideraon.
Especially since the Trump-crical journalist Ezra Klein (in contrast to Trump's remarks)
posted this quote on Facebook already on 29th January 2016 with the foresighted
remark that exactly this open greed will be an argument for Trump's elecon victory:
"This is why he's winning." Ezra Klein (as we now know) was undoubtedly right about
that. Donald Trump won the presidenal elecons, possibly because he – where other
policians as well as journalists sll feel compelled to at least maintain certain moral
standards – quite openly describes the driving force of our society: greed, since
anquity condemned as socially endangering and disintegrang, declared by Chrisanity
as one of the seven deadly sins, today a cardinal virtue that makes elecon victory
possible. Free with Kurt Vonnegut: That's how it works.
At least Trump cannot be accused of lying - at the latest since Augusne not a mortal
sin, but a serious sin. Which may be a reason for his elecon victory. It will now be
difficult for policians and the press to deal with this man and the polical
establishment he stands for, and we can be curious to see how the public polical scene
and the newspapers will react to this. The public bustle of policians and journalists will
now have to take a new direcon. We are curious. For a cynic "to whom nothing human
is alien”, these are interesng mes, especially because – as Balthasar Gracian has put it
in his Art of Worldly Wisdom: "More is now required to deal with a single human being
in these mes than with an enre people in previous mes.”
Nevertheless, this quotaon from Donald Trump makes one think and is (if we are not
yet complete cynics) depressing. Aſter all, in the past almost all philosophers and
policians spoke out against greed and condemned it with the strongest words.
Aristotle had already cricized it in his Nicomachean Ethics as Pleonexia, the constant
urge to get more, with powerful words throughout history. Aristotle's cricism of greed,
pleonexia, the desire to have more than you ever need, is based on an understanding of
the polical which our society no longer shares, but whose opposite (and with Trump's
successful words quite obviously) even seems to be the driving force and move behind
all acons.
Aristotle discusses pleonexia in the fiſth book of his Nicomachean Ethics in relaon to
jusce. For Aristotle, jusce is the highest of all virtues, because it is essenal and
necessary for the good and orderly coexistence of the cizens of a city or country. It is
the polical virtue par excellence. Without jusce, no polical coexistence is possible for
Aristotle, since the goal (telos) of man is in the polical organizaon:
"This is why jusce is considered the most important of all virtues, and neither the
evening star nor the morning star is so wonderful. In the proverb it is said 'Every virtue is
contained in righteousness'. And it is considered most of all perfect goodness of
character, because it is the exercise of perfect goodness. But it is perfect, because the
one who possesses it can also use the virtues in relaon to another human being, and
not only for himself. [...] Therefore, the saying of Bias that the exercise of a polical
office shows what kind of person someone is, is correct. For the one who holds a
polical office is already related to the other person and is already in a community. [...]
Jusce in this sense is now not a part of goodness of character, but the whole goodness,
and injusce as opposed to it is not a only part of badness, but the whole badness.”
Greed – let us follow Aristotle – destroys jusce and thus the polical foundaon on
which a society is based, which is why for Aristotle it is not only "a part of badness, but
all badness". For this reason, he condemns in the strictest terms those who strive for
more – the pleonektes, the greedy – because they want more than they deserve (in
relaon to the other cizens), which is why they are unjust and destrucve to society:
"On the one hand, those who violate the law (paranomos) are considered unjust, and on
the other hand those, who want more than they are entled to ( pleonektes), i.e. who
have an atude of inequality. [...] Since now the unjust wants to have more, he will
have to deal with goods, not with all goods, but with those to which outer happiness
(eutychia) and misfortune (atychia) refer, thus with goods which as such are always
goods, but not in every case for every man. People ask for them in prayers and chase
aſter them. However, they should not do this, but rather they should ask that the things
that are goods in themselves are also goods for them, and then choose these.”
For Aristotle, greed – pleonexia – Is the highest form of injusce and thus the worst of
all vices, because it endangers the existence of a polical community. This is especially
true when leading polical officials are greedy and place parcular interests above the
common good. In Aristotle's concepon, the polical community of his me (the polis)
did not consist primarily in economic independence (as our understanding today
suggests) and in maximizing the profits of the individuals/instuons living in a polical
community (also these modern terms), but rather in securing a common and thus good
polical life for the cizens, which the hedonist endangers through his exaggerated
desire to have more than the others.
Even if the Romans generally dealt with moral and polical quesons more loosely than
their Greek predecessors, the (at least public) condemnaon of greed remained a basic
component of the polical discussion at that me. In this sense, Cicero (exemplary as
the best known public figure to us) already addressed the vice of greed in his work On
Dues (De officiis), in parcular in relaon to the officials important for each state.
Especially officials should not be out to enrich themselves personally, because –
following Aristotle – this leads to unjust acons, which endanger the existence of a
community:
"No vice is more repulsive than greed, especially among leading men and those who run
the state. To have the state as a source of income is not only shameful, but also criminal
and nefarious. […] But those who are at the head of the state cannot win the
benevolence of many more easily by any means than by absnence and self-control.”
Also for the Stoa and Epicureanism, as well as for the enre ancient philosophy greed
remained the basic evil par excellence, with the same argumentaon that we already
got to know from Aristotle and Cicero: Because it is unfair, puts personal interests above
the welfare of the community, and thus leads to profoundly apolical and asocial
results, which dissolves an exisng polical system: with all the resulng consequences
that are known in history (all this is not new, one reads only Thucydides, Plutarch and
Sueton for the Greek respecvely Roman anquity or Montaigne, Hobbes and
Grimmelshausen for the beginning of the modern era) and which are now announcing
themselves to us again.
Likewise, greed was of course condemned in Chrisanity, albeit less as polical
misconduct, but rather as a personal sin endangering the salvaon of the soul, which
was mostly characterized as an inordinate striving for earthly possessions and as a lack
of trust in God. Greed (avaria; cupiditas) belongs both to the catalogue of the seven
main vices and to the three temptaons. Following the biblical passage 1 Timothy 6:
"Greed is the root of all evil" greed was described as bad in itself. Moreover, on the
basis of Jacob 5 it was even condemned as a "blatant sin" which was even worse than
the deadly sins because greed promoted the exploitaon of the workers. Jacob says:
“Now listen, you rich people, weep and wail because of the misery that is coming on
you. Your wealth has roed, and moths have eaten your clothes. Your gold and silver are
corroded. Their corrosion will tesfy against you and eat your flesh like fire. You have
hoarded wealth in the last days. Look! The wages you failed to pay the workers who
mowed your fields are crying out against you. The cries of the harvesters have reached
the ears of the Lord Almighty. You have lived on earth in luxury and self-indulgence. You
have faened yourselves in the day of slaughter. You have condemned and murdered
the innocent one, who was not opposing you.”
In the Middle Ages, the cricism of greed received an even deeper weighng as a
reacon to the bourgeois economy of money and goods that had developed. In the 12th and 13th centuries, the mendicant orders of the Dominicans and Franciscans were
founded (each as a reacon to changing polical and economic circumstances), whose
principles of poverty (paupertas) were completely opposed to greed. Take for example a
text wrien in the middle of the 13th century: in this text Saint Francis himself goes in
search of poverty, which is called the "foundaon of all virtues" ( fundamentum omnium
virtutum). In her speech, poverty complains about the fact that her opponent, avaria,
understood as "an inordinate desire to acquire or retain wealth", masquerades under
the names of "disncon" ( discreo) and "foresight" (providena) – which we will sll
encounter in Hobbes – and corrupts people.
Here one could sll add infinitely many examples of the me, from Thomas of Aquinas
to Dante Alighieri, who leaves the desirous in the Divine comedy with their backs up in
the dust, because they are not allowed to look at God, to Bernardine of Siena, whose
sermons Poggio Bracciolini in Florence had used as an occasion to write in 1428 with his
Dialogue On Greed (De avaria) probably the most important trease of the
Renaissance on this subject. The point is clear: since anquity greed has been
condemned unl the late Middle Ages and the Renaissance because – following these
authors – It has been dangerous for society and disintegrang for each individual.
This view of man, his goals and human coexistence in general changed for the first me
systemacally and philosophically with Thomas Hobbes, whom we can see as the
theorist of a modern society, in whose wake (though probably without knowing it)
Donald Trump sll stands with his public affirmaon of greed – with the difference, of
course, that Hobbes' books were burned in Oxford while Donald Trump was applauded
for it. Machiavelli had already hinted at a new view of the human being, the polical as
a sector in its own – In which greed plays a fundamental and acon-movang role –
and its goals in his Principe and Discorsi, but Thomas Hobbes for the first me in his
Leviathan theorecally founded and analyzed the concept of a society in which we sll
live: A property market society in which atomized and completely dissociated individuals
meet, who are only held together by overcoming their respecve self-interest – which
Hobbes no longer quesons, but (due to and in extension of his experiences during the
English Civil War) is assumed to be given factually in the nature of man – by a strong
sovereign, the only power "that can frighten them all", in order to realize a single
polical goal: The desire for peace, which (according to Hobbes) can only be realized
through the limitaon of the greed of each individual, which is presumed in human
beings, by a strong sovereign.
In order to make clear this fundamentally new view of man and the emergence of
society at Hobbes, I will only allow myself to contrast Hobbes with Rousseau: At the
beginning of the second chapter of the Social Contract, Rousseau writes: "The oldest
and only natural social enty is the family [...]". Hobbes writes in De cive [On the
cizen], summarizing, as it were, the core of his enre anthropology: "We now want to
go back to the state of nature and assume that humans, like mushrooms, would
suddenly have grown out of the earth and grown up, without being obliged to each
other.” For Hobbes there is no polical goal to be realized among mankind, no
acceptance of man as a polical being who makes his life a fulfiled and happy life only
in living together with others. For Hobbes – who here subconsciously or consciously
describes his (and also our) me in the form of the "state of nature" – there is no happy
life anymore. There is only the limitaon of greed with all available means – mind you:
against human beings and their egoisc parcular interests, which are assumed to be
eternal, their striving for the will to have more and more.
This is the first me in history that Hobbes has clearly formulated and worked out the
drive of his and our me: According to Hobbes, what drives people, what only leads
them to create "that great Leviathan through art, called community or state," is
precisely that passion that has been condemned since anquity as pleonexia, as avaria,
as greed. Man submits to an overpowering state in order to be safe from his own greed
and the greed of others and not to have to be afraid anymore: The state as
administrator of our fear, the undisturbed enrichment as its basis. But behind this is also
the feeling that society is already so fluid or fragile that the behaviour of overly greedy
people forces all others to take part in the race for power over others. This
consideraon is both terrible and overwhelming: it is that arficial "let's make man"
which Hobbes was the first to think systemacally and clearly – with great concern and
deep aversion – and which he formulated as an aempt to overcome the terrible
condions of his me; and which is now the driving force and basis of our society: "My
whole life I've been greedy, greedy, greedy. I've grabbed all the money I could get. I'm
so greedy." With greed elecons are won today, this is the way polics is made today
quite openly.
Accordingly, John Locke and Adam Smith were to turn this brutal diagnosis, which
Hobbes sll formulated with concern and deep aversion, into a posive one only a lile
later and make it socially acceptable in public: Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Senments
(1759) describes how those who pursue only their own advantage are led by an
"invisible hand", so that they "without intending it, indeed without knowing it promote
the interest of society". And in his work The Wealth of Naons he formulates the
assumpon – destrucve for all of us in his succession and not only reckless, but
inhuman – that self-interest is the "cause and source" of public prosperity.
Here we have arrived – oppressively – in our me. In a present in which greed is not
only publicly declared a virtue with which the world is governed and with which
elecons are won, but also in which all other vices condemned for centuries seem to
have become virtues.
For the seven deadly sins are well known: lust, gluony, greed, sloth, wrath, envy and
pride. These sins – sll condemned in the latest Catechism of the Catholic Church –
seem to be the very qualies with which the world is currently governed and to which a
large part of the people – subconsciously or quite consciously, thus confirming Hobbes'
diagnosis – have subordinated themselves. These sins have become the motor of
modern society: "All my life I was greedy, greedy, greedy. I grabbed all the money I
could get. But now I want to be greedy for the United States. I want to collect all that
money. I will be greedy for the United States."
To close this arcle not with Donald Trump and his promise to his constuents, but with
a much older warning: "Watch out for false prophets. They come to you in sheep’s
clothing, but inwardly they are ferocious wolves. By their fruit you will recognize them."
This is a warning that will also have been wrien in the two Bibles on which Donald
Trump laid his hand during his inauguraon.
For more information:
http://www.freetranslations.foundation
Add Your Comments
We are 100% volunteer and depend on your participation to sustain our efforts!
Get Involved
If you'd like to help with maintaining or developing the website, contact us.
Publish
Publish your stories and upcoming events on Indybay.
Topics
More
Search Indybay's Archives
Advanced Search
►
▼
IMC Network